hn-classics/_stories/2006/10888893.md

10 KiB
Raw Blame History

created_at title url author points story_text comment_text num_comments story_id story_title story_url parent_id created_at_i _tags objectID
2016-01-12T17:43:03.000Z A new proof of Euclid's Theorem (2006) http://fermatslibrary.com/s/a-new-proof-of-euclids-theorem bezierc 56 31 1452620583
story
author_bezierc
story_10888893
10888893

Source

Fermat's Library | A new proof of Euclid's Theorem annotated/explained version.

FERMAT'S LIBRARY

Enter your email to receive a new paper every week:

Close

Join our newsletter to receive a new paper every week

Close

FERMAT'S LIBRARY

Help us pay for server costs by donating below

Donate Bitcoin:

1KrAD3NvReo819SYa2v6MMCeKRBsJH81Mo

Donate Ethereum:

0x5b8b23aCAE57168c00960f07544CFB22a797d7C9

Donate Litecoin:

Le5a453VL1qSN7dekKCgJiCqx2yNXE3f7U

Comments

__

Ask a question or post a comment about the paper

Join the discussion! Ask questions and share your comments.

Sign in with Google
Sign in with Facebook
Sign in with email

__

Get direct links to references, BibTeX extraction and comments on all arXiv papers with: ** __ Librarian **

Euclid's Theorem is one of the fundamental results in number theory...

In this paper Filip Saidak, Professor at The University of North Ca...

Q = p_1.p_2...p_k + 1= P+1 is either prime or not. 1. If Q i...

Why are you not specific here. Just pick one, say 2.

Two numbers are coprime if their highest common factor (or greatest...

Besides being a concise constructive proof, Saidak's relies solely ...

This is another incomplete argument. Be precise: "which process" an...

IMO you are not giving a complete argument here. If you spell out t...

American Math. Monthly, Vol 113, No. 10, December 2006.

A NEW PROOF OF EUCLID'S THEOREM

FILIP SAIDAK

A prime number is an integer greater than 1 that is divisible only

by 1 and itself. Mathematicians have been studying primes and their

properties for over twenty-three centuries. One of the very first results

concerning these numbers was presumably proved by Euclid of Alexan-

dria, sometime before 300 B.C. In Book IX of his legendary Elements

(see 2) we find Proposition 20, which states:

Proposition. There are infinitely many prime numbers.

Euclid's proof (modernized). Assume to the contrary that the set

P of all prime numbers is finite, say P = {p

1

, p

2

, · · · , p

k

} for a positive

integer k. If Q := (p

1

p

2

· · · p

k

)+1, then gcd(Q, p

i

) = 1 for i = 1, 2, · · · k.

Therefore Q has to have a prime factor different from all existing primes.

That is a contradiction. 

Today many proofs of Euclid's theorem are known. It may come as a

surprise that the following almost trivial argument has not been given

before:

New proof. Let n be an arbitrary positive integer greater than 1. Since

n and n + 1 are consecutive integers, they must be coprime. Hence the

number N

2

= n(n + 1) must have at least two different prime factors.

Similarly, since the integers n(n+1) and n(n+1)+1 are consecutive, and

therefore coprime, the number N

3

= n(n + 1)[n(n + 1) + 1] must have

at least three different prime factors. This process can be continued

indefinitely, so the number of primes must be infinite. 

1

Analysis. The proof just given is conceptually even simpler than the

original proof due to Euclid, since it does not use Eudoxus's method of

"reductio ad absurdum," proof by contradiction. And unlike most other

proofs of the theorem, it does not require Proposition 30 of Elements

(sometimes called "Euclid's Lemma") that states: if p is a prime and

p|ab, then either p|a or p|b. Moreover, our proof is constructive, and it

gives integers with an arbitrary number of prime factors.

Remarks. In Ribenboim [4, pp.311] and Narkiewicz [3, pp.110] one

finds at least a dozen different proofs of the classical theorem of Euclid,

and many other variations of the arguments listed in 1, 3, and 4 have

been published over the years (in chronological order) by: Goldbach

(1730), Euler (1737 and 1762), Kummer (1878), Perott (1881), Stieltjes

(1890), Thue (1897), Brocard (1915), P´olya (1921), Erd˝os (1938), Bell-

man (1947), F¨urstenberg (1955), Barnes (1976), Washington (1980),

and others. Goldbach's proof (see 4, p.4), which uses pairwise copri-

mality of Fermat numbers, seems to be closest in spirit to the argument

we have presented.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS. Personal and virtual conversations with

Professors Paulo Ribenboim (Queen's University) and Eduard Kos-

tolansky (Bratislava) are gratefully acknowledged. I would also like to

thank Professor W ladyslaw Narkiewicz (Wroclaw) for bringing to my

attention Hermite's very simple proof concerning n! + 1.

References

1 M. Aigner and G. M. & Ziegler, Proofs from THE BOOK, Springer-Verlag, Berlin,

1999

2 T. L. Heath,The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements, vol. 2, University Press,

Cambridge, 1908; 2nd ed. reprinted by Dover, New York, 1956.

3 W. Narkiewicz, The Development of Prime Number Theory, Springer-Verlag, New

York, 2000

4 P. Ribenboim, The New Book of Prime Number Records, Springer-Verlag, New York,

1996

2

Please enable JavaScript to view the comments powered by Disqus.

__

Discussion

@Heinrich The implicit claim is that N_i contains at least i different prime factors. N_i + 1 is coprime with N_i, so it has geq 1 prime factor different from the geq i different prime factors in N_i. Thus, N_{i+1} := N_i (N_i + 1) has geq i+1 different prime factors. Together with the base case that N_1 := n > 1 has at least one prime factor, this proves the claim via induction. Euclid's Theorem is one of the fundamental results in number theory, which asserts that there are infinitely many prime numbers. The first proof of Euclid's Theorem was in the 9th book of Euclid's geometric treatise ( Elements) in 300 B.C. . The frontispiece of Sir Henry Billingsley's first English version of Euclid's Elements, 1570 Figure: The frontispiece of Sir Henry Billingsley's first English version of Euclid's Elements, 1570 This is another incomplete argument. Be precise: "which process" and why are the generated numbers different from each other? Why should there be 3 different prime factors? Why are you not specific here. Just pick one, say 2. Saidak's new proof seems awfully similar to his restatement of Euclid's proof. In both cases the key is that any finite set of primes {p_1, p_2, ..., p_n} can be extended by appending the prime factors of p_1p_2(...)p_n+1, which don't belong to {p_1, ..., p_n}. Daniel Roca González: Yes. Besides being a concise constructive proof, Saidak's relies solely on the property that consecutive integers are coprime and that's what makes this proof unique. And even if there were three, why can't two of them coincede? E.g. 2 cdot 2 cdot 3 ? You are not giving a complete argument here. Coprime means that two numbers share no common prime factors. n and n+1 share no prime factors, so n(n+1) must have at least 2 prime factors. Consequently, the number after n(n+1), n(n+1)+1 shares no common factors with n(n+1), so it must share no common factors with either n or n+1 since you can't get new prime factors by multiplying together n and n+1 Two numbers are coprime if their highest common factor (or greatest common divisor) is 1. IMO you are not giving a complete argument here. If you spell out the details to make it rigorous by modern standards, you will likely need more then half a page. Euclids proof, on the other hand is super clean and concise. While Euclid's proof is usually reworded like this, it is not actually necessary to use contradiction in this way. Instead of assuming P is the finite set of all prime numbers, you can take P to be any finite set of primes, and follow in the same way. The proof shows that Q has a prime factor which is not in P, which already proves the premise since P was arbitrary. You can use this iteratively(just put the new prime in the set P and apply the proof again to get a new prime) to generate an infinite set of primes, just like Saidak's proof, and it's just as simple. Thx @Erik for spelling it out. I think this argument deserves a little more elaboration than just "Similarly" in a proof of an elementary result, that should be digestible by beginners. In this paper Filip Saidak, Professor at The University of North Carolina at Greensboro, comes up with a proof that is conceptually even simpler than Euclid's proof. Euclid's Theorem has been proved by several other famous mathematicians including Euler and Paul Erdos. Euler's and Erdo's proofs relied on the fundamental theorem of arithmetic: that every integer has a unique prime factorization. To see their proofs click here Q = p_1.p_2...p_k + 1= P+1 is either prime or not. 1. If Q is prime then by contradiction there's one more prime in the set P 2. If Q is not prime, there is a p_i in the set P that divides Q. By definition, since p_i is in the list it will also divide P. If p_i divides Q and P it will also divide its difference Q-P=1, which is a contradiction since no prime number divides 1. This means that p_i is a prime number and can't be in the list! As can be seen, Euclid proves the result by contradiction, assuming that the initial set P contains all the prime numbers. Saidak's proof unlike Euclid's avoids the "reductio ad absurdum" method.